forked from kosukeimai/qss
-
Notifications
You must be signed in to change notification settings - Fork 0
/
fp75.txt
152 lines (151 loc) · 12.4 KB
/
fp75.txt
1
2
3
4
5
6
7
8
9
10
11
12
13
14
15
16
17
18
19
20
21
22
23
24
25
26
27
28
29
30
31
32
33
34
35
36
37
38
39
40
41
42
43
44
45
46
47
48
49
50
51
52
53
54
55
56
57
58
59
60
61
62
63
64
65
66
67
68
69
70
71
72
73
74
75
76
77
78
79
80
81
82
83
84
85
86
87
88
89
90
91
92
93
94
95
96
97
98
99
100
101
102
103
104
105
106
107
108
109
110
111
112
113
114
115
116
117
118
119
120
121
122
123
124
125
126
127
128
129
130
131
132
133
134
135
136
137
138
139
140
141
142
143
144
145
146
147
148
149
150
151
152
THE President is to have power, "by and with the advice and consent of
the Senate, to make treaties, provided two thirds of the senators present
concur." Though this provision has been assailed, on different grounds, with no
small degree of vehemence, I scruple not to declare my firm persuasion,
that it is one of the best digested and most unexceptionable parts of
the plan. One ground of objection is the trite topic of the intermixture
of powers; some contending that the President ought alone to possess the
power of making treaties; others, that it ought to have been exclusively
deposited in the Senate. Another source of objection is derived from the
small number of persons by whom a treaty may be made. Of those who espouse
this objection, a part are of opinion that the House of Representatives
ought to have been associated in the business, while another part seem
to think that nothing more was necessary than to have substituted two
thirds of ALL the members of the Senate, to two thirds of the members
PRESENT. As I flatter myself the observations made in a preceding number
upon this part of the plan must have sufficed to place it, to a discerning
eye, in a very favorable light, I shall here content myself with offering
only some supplementary remarks, principally with a view to the objections
which have been just stated. With regard to the intermixture of powers, I shall rely upon the explanations
already given in other places, of the true sense of the rule upon which
that objection is founded; and shall take it for granted, as an inference
from them, that the union of the Executive with the Senate, in the article
of treaties, is no infringement of that rule. I venture to add, that the
particular nature of the power of making treaties indicates a peculiar
propriety in that union. Though several writers on the subject of government
place that power in the class of executive authorities, yet this is evidently
an arbitrary disposition; for if we attend carefully to its operation,
it will be found to partake more of the legislative than of the executive
character, though it does not seem strictly to fall within the definition
of either of them. The essence of the legislative authority is to enact
laws, or, in other words, to prescribe rules for the regulation of the
society; while the execution of the laws, and the employment of the common
strength, either for this purpose or for the common defense, seem to comprise
all the functions of the executive magistrate. The power of making treaties
is, plainly, neither the one nor the other. It relates neither to the
execution of the subsisting laws, nor to the enaction of new ones; and
still less to an exertion of the common strength. Its objects are CONTRACTS
with foreign nations, which have the force of law, but derive it from
the obligations of good faith. They are not rules prescribed by the sovereign
to the subject, but agreements between sovereign and sovereign. The power
in question seems therefore to form a distinct department, and to belong,
properly, neither to the legislative nor to the executive. The qualities
elsewhere detailed as indispensable in the management of foreign negotiations,
point out the Executive as the most fit agent in those transactions; while
the vast importance of the trust, and the operation of treaties as laws,
plead strongly for the participation of the whole or a portion of the
legislative body in the office of making them. However proper or safe it may be in governments where the executive magistrate
is an hereditary monarch, to commit to him the entire power of making
treaties, it would be utterly unsafe and improper to intrust that power
to an elective magistrate of four years' duration. It has been remarked,
upon another occasion, and the remark is unquestionably just, that an
hereditary monarch, though often the oppressor of his people, has personally
too much stake in the government to be in any material danger of being
corrupted by foreign powers. But a man raised from the station of a private
citizen to the rank of chief magistrate, possessed of a moderate or slender
fortune, and looking forward to a period not very remote when he may probably
be obliged to return to the station from which he was taken, might sometimes
be under temptations to sacrifice his duty to his interest, which it would
require superlative virtue to withstand. An avaricious man might be tempted
to betray the interests of the state to the acquisition of wealth. An
ambitious man might make his own aggrandizement, by the aid of a foreign
power, the price of his treachery to his constituents. The history of
human conduct does not warrant that exalted opinion of human virtue which
would make it wise in a nation to commit interests of so delicate and
momentous a kind, as those which concern its intercourse with the rest
of the world, to the sole disposal of a magistrate created and circumstanced
as would be a President of the United States. To have intrusted the power of making treaties to the Senate alone, would
have been to relinquish the benefits of the constitutional agency of the
President in the conduct of foreign negotiations. It is true that the
Senate would, in that case, have the option of employing him in this capacity,
but they would also have the option of letting it alone, and pique or
cabal might induce the latter rather than the former. Besides this, the
ministerial servant of the Senate could not be expected to enjoy the confidence
and respect of foreign powers in the same degree with the constitutional
representatives of the nation, and, of course, would not be able to act
with an equal degree of weight or efficacy. While the Union would, from
this cause, lose a considerable advantage in the management of its external
concerns, the people would lose the additional security which would result
from the co-operation of the Executive. Though it would be imprudent to
confide in him solely so important a trust, yet it cannot be doubted that
his participation would materially add to the safety of the society. It
must indeed be clear to a demonstration that the joint possession of the
power in question, by the President and Senate, would afford a greater
prospect of security, than the separate possession of it by either of
them. And whoever has maturely weighed the circumstances which must concur
in the appointment of a President, will be satisfied that the office will
always bid fair to be filled by men of such characters as to render their
concurrence in the formation of treaties peculiarly desirable, as well
on the score of wisdom, as on that of integrity. The remarks made in a former number, which have been alluded to in another
part of this paper, will apply with conclusive force against the admission
of the House of Representatives to a share in the formation of treaties.
The fluctuating and, taking its future increase into the account, the
multitudinous composition of that body, forbid us to expect in it those
qualities which are essential to the proper execution of such a trust.
Accurate and comprehensive knowledge of foreign politics; a steady and
systematic adherence to the same views; a nice and uniform sensibility
to national character; decision, SECRECY, and despatch, are incompatible
with the genius of a body so variable and so numerous. The very complication
of the business, by introducing a necessity of the concurrence of so many
different bodies, would of itself afford a solid objection. The greater
frequency of the calls upon the House of Representatives, and the greater
length of time which it would often be necessary to keep them together
when convened, to obtain their sanction in the progressive stages of a
treaty, would be a source of so great inconvenience and expense as alone
ought to condemn the project. The only objection which remains to be canvassed, is that which would
substitute the proportion of two thirds of all the members composing the
senatorial body, to that of two thirds of the members PRESENT. It has
been shown, under the second head of our inquiries, that all provisions
which require more than the majority of any body to its resolutions, have
a direct tendency to embarrass the operations of the government, and an
indirect one to subject the sense of the majority to that of the minority.
This consideration seems sufficient to determine our opinion, that the
convention have gone as far in the endeavor to secure the advantage of
numbers in the formation of treaties as could have been reconciled either
with the activity of the public councils or with a reasonable regard to
the major sense of the community. If two thirds of the whole number of
members had been required, it would, in many cases, from the non-attendance
of a part, amount in practice to a necessity of unanimity. And the history
of every political establishment in which this principle has prevailed,
is a history of impotence, perplexity, and disorder. Proofs of this position
might be adduced from the examples of the Roman Tribuneship, the Polish
Diet, and the States-General of the Netherlands, did not an example at
home render foreign precedents unnecessary. To require a fixed proportion of the whole body would not, in all probability,
contribute to the advantages of a numerous agency, better then merely
to require a proportion of the attending members. The former, by making
a determinate number at all times requisite to a resolution, diminishes
the motives to punctual attendance. The latter, by making the capacity
of the body to depend on a PROPORTION which may be varied by the absence
or presence of a single member, has the contrary effect. And as, by promoting
punctuality, it tends to keep the body complete, there is great likelihood
that its resolutions would generally be dictated by as great a number
in this case as in the other; while there would be much fewer occasions
of delay. It ought not to be forgotten that, under the existing Confederation,
two members MAY, and usually DO, represent a State; whence it happens
that Congress, who now are solely invested with ALL THE POWERS of the
Union, rarely consist of a greater number of persons than would compose
the intended Senate. If we add to this, that as the members vote by States,
and that where there is only a single member present from a State, his
vote is lost, it will justify a supposition that the active voices in
the Senate, where the members are to vote individually, would rarely fall
short in number of the active voices in the existing Congress. When, in
addition to these considerations, we take into view the co-operation of
the President, we shall not hesitate to infer that the people of America
would have greater security against an improper use of the power of making
treaties, under the new Constitution, than they now enjoy under the Confederation.
And when we proceed still one step further, and look forward to the probable
augmentation of the Senate, by the erection of new States, we shall not
only perceive ample ground of confidence in the sufficiency of the members
to whose agency that power will be intrusted, but we shall probably be
led to conclude that a body more numerous than the Senate would be likely
to become, would be very little fit for the proper discharge of the trust.